Greek Thoughts, Indian Roots?

A few weeks ago, I came across Sanjeev Sabhlok’s article on how (and why) the ideas of liberty – so celebrated in the western world today – may actually have had their origins in India.

Sanjeev has lucidly argued for the case and there is really nothing much I can add – except to say that this aspect is certainly worthy of further research and will help us shape the pieces defining the extraordinary civilisation and culture that flourished milleniums ago in this ancient land.

Below, excerpts from Sanjeev’s article on (how) Greek thought, the harbinger of world liberty – has its direct source in INDIA (emphasis mine).

*** Excerpts Begin (Caution: Long Post) ***

…When, upon reading A Critical History of Greek Philosophy by W.T. Stace (MacMillan,1965) I came across his rather niggardly view on Indian philosophy, arguing that Indian thought doesn’t arise from ‘pure thought’ and that it is ‘poetic rather than scientific’ (p.15), I decided to investigate further. I have now found a recent American PhD dissertation (2000) that uses the most recent sources to firmly demonstrate that it was INDIAN scepticism that traveled to Greece through Persia and brought out the temperament of questioning that finally led to Socrates.

…Does it matter to me whether humanity has benefited in the areas of mathematics (number system) and philosophy more from India than from, say, Greece? I’m not particularly fussed where the source is, India or Greece. These ideas belong to all of us. Humanity. No country owns them, at least not today. What I do want, though, is accurate attribution of sources. It won’t do to attribute the first seeds of rational thought in the world to Greece when these ideas arose in India, and were transmitted by Indians to the Greeks.

Extract from The Untold Story about Greek Rational Thought: Buddhist and Other Indian Rationalist Influences on Sophist Rhetoricby BASNAGODA RAHULA (thanks to Sanjeev for doing the painful conversion from pdf to text and formatting it back again):

General Signs of Indian Influence on Protagoras and Gorgias

Three factors may justify the possibility that the unusual resemblance of Indian rationalist thoughts to Greek sophist thinking was caused by a connection between the two societies. First, Protagoras, the alleged father of Greek sophistry, was given Persian education, an easy route to the access of Indian wisdom. During Xerxes’ invasion of Greece, Protagoras’ father, an extremely rich person in Abdera, entertained Xerxes and received the emperor’s permission to educate Protagoras under Magi….Based on the traditional practice of the pupil’s visiting the master, one may conclude that Protagoras later went to Susa and studied under Magi. This visit would have been more profitable for Protagoras since he would hardly miss Indian wisdom those days in the central part of the Persian empire. On the other hand, wherever Protagoras was educated, knowledge coming from Persia could have included Indian thinking since Darius had already accommodated, as the next chapter will elucidate, Indian wisdom in the Persian empire.

Second, Protagoras was the pupil of Democritus who was presumably benefited by a multitude of Indian concepts, including Buddhist concepts as his major source of influence. …Protagoras’ closeness in his epistemological studies to the Indian counterparts will be discussed later, but here it should be briefly stated that Democritus’ possible Indian influence could hardly leave no marks on his pupil Protagoras.

Third, Gorgias was the student of Empedocles, whose philosophical theories reflect his possible familiarity with Indian idealistic and rationalistic views.

The major aspects of sophist rational thought and their similarity with the Indian counterpart will be discussed in separate sections, but it seems apt to highlight here a unique flavor in argumentation entertained by Protagoras-the flavor for arguing for or/and against any topic-as a possible Indian derivation. Perhaps this hypothesis appears to be an overstatement since argument on probabilities is said to be of Greek origin. Nevertheless, a careful examination of the practices in Indian debating during the sixth century B.C.E. and comparison of those practices with Protagoras’ attitude towards argumentation justify the possibility of this hypothesis.

Interestingly, there was a group of Indian debaters namely Vitandavadins who roamed among all sorts of thinkers and challenged other views. “He [a Vitandavadin] had no views of his own but merely indulged in eristic for the purpose of securing victory in argument” (Jayatilleke 217). Even though the word Vitandavadin did not occur in the Sutta Pitaka, one finds numerous examples that during the sixth century B.C.E. these debaters frequented debating halls, parks, and other meeting places, challenging all sorts of views of other traditions, without maintaining any particular philosophy or theory of their own:

There are recluses and Brahmins who are clever, subtle, experienced in controversy, hair-splitters, who go about breaking to pieces by their intelligence [pannagatena] the speculations of others. Were I to pronounce this to be good, or that to be evil, these men might join issue with me, call upon me for my reasons, and point out my errors.’

These remarks suggest that those “recluses and Brahmins” were not those who held any particular view or theory but those who were indulged in debating rarely for the sake of defeating the opponents and establishing rhetorical power. Whatever concept or theory one held, those debaters opposed one’s position using their intelligence and verbal skill. This practice is farther confirmed by the sentence, “Some recluse or Brahmin is addicted to logic and reasoning.”

.

Saccaka, who earned the description of “one who indulged in debate, a learned controversialist, who was held in high esteem by the common people” was, undoubtedly, one of them. The Majjima Nikaya has preserved a very important sentence that reflects his theoretical practice and skill:

If I attacked a lifeless pillar with my language, it [the pillar] would totter, tremble, quake; how much more a human being!’

Saccaka was more a demonstration of his verbal power than a theorist. Here, he has presented no theory, but simply boasts about his invincible rhetorical power. ‘Whoever he argued with, he defeated the opponent’s theory without insisting on a particular view of his own but only using his verbal skill (eristic) and argumentation (antilogic) that would suit to the occasion.

The Samyutta Nikaya has provided “an eye-witness’s account of these recluses and Brahmins in action” (Jayatilleke 221). Kundaliya, a visitor to the Buddha’s monastery, told the Buddha that he (Kundaliya) would visit parks and frequent assemblies as a regular habit because he had found interest in seeing some recluses and Brahmins having being engaged in debates. The purpose of those debates was only to emphasize their own argumentation (itivadapa mokkhanisamsam) and to disparage that of others.” All this evidence indicates that debating for the mere sake of reflecting the opposition had become a prevalent practice, as well as a crowd-gathering entertainment, during the time of the Buddha. The topics reportedly argued about by those controversialists speak a volume of this peculiar practice of debating. Most of the topics were in pairs, representing the thesis and the antithesis of the same subject. The following is the first list of such topics given in Pali texts. The fact that they were originally in pairs is confirmed by the remarks attested to one particular pair of topics:

  1. The universe is eternal/The universe is not eternal.
  2. The universe is finite/The universe is not finite.
  3. The soul is identical with the body/The soul is different from the body.
  4. The enlightened person exists after death/The enlightened person does not exist after death.
  5. An enlightened person does and does not exist after death/An enlightened person neither exists nor does not exist after death.'”

A more expanded list of thirty-one topics, all in pairs and each pair dealing with the opposite of the same subject as given above, is found in the Lankavatara Sutra.’

…It is obvious that this development of questions in pairs echoes the practice of debating, in which the mere skill in argumentation was emphasized. Debaters such as Saccaka, whose primary interest was “displaying dialectical skill and defeating their opponents, regardless of the nature of the arguments used” (Jayatilleke 219), would probably argue one day in favor of the infiniteness of the universe and the other day against it, depending on the position of his opponents. Even though some debaters actually held some theories of their own, rhetorical skill was the main weapon that they employed to attack the opposition and defend their own views. The important point here is that in India there was a predominant and widespread debating practice in which both the proponents and opponents vehemently debated on the thesis and the antithesis of the same topic, adducing equally powerful arguments.

In Greece Protagoras was the first rhetor to introduce this kind of argumentation. Laertius said that “Protagoras was the first to say that on every issue there are two arguments opposed to each other.” Clement repeated the same statement, saying that Greeks said, “Every argument has an opposite argument,” following Protagoras.” Seneca wrote, “Protagoras says that one can argue equally well on either side of any question, including the question itself whether both sides of any question can be argued.” Not only did Protagoras introduce this “eristic argument” as remarked by Hesychius,” but he also demonstrated the truth of his theory, arguing “by the method of questioning, a practice he originated.” Protagoras also “wrote down and prepared disputations on notable subjects.” Thus it is evident that Protagoras held his two-logoi theory as one of his major concepts, having introduced it, practiced it, and written treatises on it.

This theory of argumentation seems strikingly similar to the popular Indian concept of arguing for and against the same topic. Just as the topics used by Indian debaters consisted of the direct affirmation and the direct negation of the same statement, Protagoras’ topics also consisted of pairs of two extreme opposites. Similarly, the field from which these questions were drawn seems to be exactly the same for both Protagoras and the Indian debaters.

Protagoras, when once the existence of ‘two logoi in opposition to each other’ was discovered as inherent in all reality whenever one tries to consider it abstractly, translated this properly of the metaphysical world into contradictory pairs of opposites, making of it a precept for argument; that is to say, he must have demolished by dialectical arguments and with a certain systematic severity all the principle concepts created by Reason, beginning from the problem of God in order to pass on to the others. (Untersteiner 35)

Notably, Protagoras’ “contradictory pairs of opposites,” as Untersteiner has stated above, did not originate in traditional Greek rhetoric; rather, it originated in metaphysics, the field from which the Indian debaters also selected their topics. There is the possibility that Protagoras learned this practice from Democritus, who could have been very much exposed to the Indian way of debating while he was in India. One should also wonder why Protagoras was not exposed to the same theory of argumentation while he was receiving his Persian education.

A controversial situation might arise from this disclosure since the argument about probabilities has long been accepted as an essential, inherent characteristic in traditional Greek rhetoric. It should be repeated, however, that the origin of systematic persuasion in Sicily was a little over two decades old when Protagoras came to Athens, and whatever arguments on probabilities that might have existed in Sicily before Protagoras began his rational persuasion in Athens was probably in legal discourses. Contradictory references to the existence of argument about probabilities in Sicily would make this second assumption even more doubtful. Plato, referring to the example of a weakling’s assault on a strong man, indicated that Tisias argued about probabilities in legal discourses. However, Aristotle cited the same example to suggest that Corax, not Tisias, argued on probabilities in legal speeches. In contrast to both, Cicero, relying on another Aristotelian source that is now lost, remarked that Corax and Tisias prepared only a handbook for the civilians to regain their (civilians’) lost property from the fallen tyrants.” Another alleged reference is that Corax “developed a tripartite scheme of oratory to help the citizens speak in the assembly” (Kennedy, Art of Persuasion in Greece 59). However, no argument about probabilities was ever mentioned in this scheme of oratory that was invented at least a decade after the origin of judiciary discourses. If whatever persuasion on probabilities ever achieved any importance in Sicily before Protagoras entered upon rational argumentation in Athens, that would probably be only in legal speeches.

As noted in the introduction, when Gorgias and Tisias visited Athens about three decades after Corax and Tisias prepared the earliest handbook on legal discourses, Protagoras had already enkindled an interest in debates, eristic, and antilogic, using his two-logoi theory. He introduced “the method of attacking any thesis,” conducted debates, and earned the nickname “master of wrangling.”‘ His two books—The Art of Debating and Contradictory Arguments in Two Books—may further authenticate his intention and interest in this field. This rhetorical situation, which apparently had no roots in Greek culture, connects, both in appearance and content, only to the debating habits practiced by the Indian debaters during the late sixth century and the early fifth century B.C.E.

The difference between Protagoras and Sicilian Gorgias may be marked by the latter’s overemphasis on the invincible power of language, ft is apparent that Gorgias had developed this attitude towards language before he visited Athens in 427 B.C.E, as an ambassador to Leontini since his sensational speech in Athens against the impending attack on Leontini by Syracuse bears witness to his confidence in the power of language and his demonstration of that power, “Encomium on Helen” farther clarifies his attitude towards language, “Speech is a powerful lord,” which affects the mentality of all sort of people,” Words are like magic and drags that cause unbelievable changes in individuals,’ While Protagoras maintained that antilogic and eristic would empower the opposing argument, Gorgias mainly held that the power of the language itself might determine the skill in persuasion.

One may observe a close similarity between Gorgias’ emphasis on the power of words and the Indian debater Saccaka’s assertion of the same, Saccaka, as quoted above, maintained the invincible power of words, giving his own exaggerated skill of frightening a lifeless pillar with his words. Based on the awareness of the highly competitive debating background during this time, it may be assumed that there were a host of Saccakas in India, maintaining the same power of words with some variations. This widespread emphasis on the power of language might invite one to investigate a possible Indian influence on Gorgias, who also asserted the same power of words. Overemphasis of language as a tool to beat the opposition in India and to convince the opposition in Sicily was determined by the demands in each society, but the invincible, almost magical power of words might have originated from the same source.

One important clue available to suggest a transmission of this concept to Gorgias is the possibility that Gorgias’ teacher Empedocles had known about the debating practices of Saccaka and of similar Indian debaters. The discussion in the previous chapter revealed that at least two contemporaries of the Buddha-Ajita and Kacchayana­ had held the theory of elements exactly in the same form as Empedocles held it, providing strong support for Empedocles’ possible borrowing of that theory from the Indian sources. Both Ajita and Kacchayana were themselves debaters, but the vital point is that they both were engaged in debates with Saccaka…

Saccaka is made to say that when he joined them [the six famous debaters including Ajita and Kacchayana] in debates, they evaded in one way or other, shifted the topic of discussion, and showed signs of irritation, anger, and displeasure. These are among the recognized ‘occasions for censure,’ and their mention here implies that Saccaka was victorious in these debates. (Jayatilleke 219)

So the probable assumption should be that, if Ajita’s and Kacchayana’s theories of elements reached Empedocles exactly in the same form, the Greek thinker should also have heard about the debating power and practices of Saccaka, the more famous figure than the two theorists of elements. The rest is understandable. Even though one may not hear Gorgias say anything about Empedocles, it is probable that Gorgias came to know about the invincible power of words from Empedocles. This assumption will be farther justified in the next section of the present chapters when Gorgias’ theory of knowledge is evaluated in the light of Indian skepticism.

The lives of the other sophist thinkers except of Critias are surprisingly obscure; little is known other than the reports that several of them were the pupils of either Protagoras or Gorgias. Nothing is known about Thrasymachus other than that he came from Chalcedon in Bithynia and lived in the second half of the fifth century B.C.E. Hippias was a contemporary of Socrates, but his life is unknown except Suidas’ report that Hippias learned from virtually unknown Hegesidamus.’ Antiphon the Sophist was mixed up with two other Antiphons, and, despite having a certain collection of his writings, his early life remains unknown.

Despite the unavailability of biographical details about these sophist thinkers, strong similarities exist between their thinking and Indian thought. Particularly, the common Indian theory of knowledge and the Buddhist theories of sociology and ethics bear an undeniable resemblance with the thoughts of Prodicus, Antiphon, and Critias. Perhaps, Protagoras’ and Gorgias’ inquiry into epistemology paved the way for the rest of the sophists to continue with the same investigation. All sophist thinkers generally maintained a close relationship with other sophists. Several of Platonic dialogues have shown that sophists gathered together and held conversations together. It is possible that the younger sophist thinkers learned from more honorable Protagoras and Gorgias, whose teachers were the possible borrowers from Indian sources.

*** End of Excerpt ***

Related Post: Democracy in Ancient India… (Caution: Long Post)

B Shantanu

Political Activist, Blogger, Advisor to start-ups, Seed investor. One time VC and ex-Diplomat. Failed mushroom farmer; ex Radio Jockey. Currently involved in Reclaiming India - One Step at a Time.

You may also like...

10 Responses

  1. Salil says:

    Ambedkar made several references in the Constituent Assembly debates to the Buddhist political theories saying that modern parliamentary practices (proposing motions, censures, voting, etc) existed in Buddhist councils and monasteries much before they became popular in Europe.

  2. A says:

    I always had a deep suspicion that this would be so. By the way it is hard not to notice how a natural affinity for debating sets us “Argumentative Indians” 🙂 apart from the neighborhood. The ideological bases of many other asian societies seem to be rooted in other appeals — e.g. in considerations that are filial — related to family and community, hierarchical — obedience to a king or political authority, moral, theological etc where there is much less scope for “rational” debate (well, I am not claiming that all debate that goes on in the Indian sphere is rational!).

    On the flip sides — It is only natural that sophists and the like thrive better in India since the battle for mindshare is one of ideas and words. The Vitandavadin would be the equivalent of the paid mercenary but operating in the world of ideas, and seems to be the long lost ancestor of today’s “Spinmeisters”.

  3. gajanan says:

    This is one of the reasons, why BRA wanted Sanskrit as national language, Salil. The Tarka Shastra ( debating science) which exists in Sankrit would have got distilled to the masses from the matts and peeths, and we would have had a debating society rather than an arguementative one.

    I have posted this in another thread , to which Shantanu has acknowledged. BRA I feel was a great man , who was an indigenous Indian , experienced all sorts of discrimination, but was misunderstood a lot by many leaders then.

  4. Thanks for posting this, Shantanu.

    I had very little time to edit my post, so it is not cogent enough and when time permits I’ll revise it. The main thing to note is that this is perhaps the first time that serious evidence has been offered to demonstrate how the Greek system of thought had its roots in India.

    I am not aware of any other significant proof (not just wild claims) on this subject. Since this finding has shifted the flow of my next book quite a bit (in terms of relatively greater importance I’m now giving to Indian philosophical thought in the history of freedom than I gave it so far), I’m keen to get the best evidence I can find and not simply make wild claims. The Western mainstream is not going to accept this idea easily.

    Interestingly, Vendanta is also quite close in its scientific approach to the ancient Indian sceptics. I’m particularly impressed by the exposition of Vedantic thought by Swami Suddhananda whose lectures are almost heretical (from the ‘traditional’ Hindu perspective – at least the way I understand it so far!), demanding very high levels of critical thinking and proof. His arguments (which I’ve come across in the past month or two) are astoundingly modern.

    The great mystery I have to resolve is why, with such outstanding thought in ancient India (note that we also had our own Machiavelli in the great political philosopher, Chanakya) did India go down the path of a rigid hereditary caste system which was against the teaching of the Vedas AND the Mahabharata (Gita).

    ALL the ingredients of the modern philosophy of freedom were therefore found 2000-2500 years ago in India. What went wrong?

    Regards
    Sanjeev

  5. B Shantanu says:

    Salil, A, Gajanan: Thanks for sharing your thoughts.

    ***

    @ Gajanan: Re. “BRA I feel was a great man , who was an indigenous Indian , experienced all sorts of discrimination, but was misunderstood a lot by many leaders then.” Well said.

    ***
    Sanjeev: Thanks for allowing me to post this on my blog..I will look forward to a revised edition!

    Will comment on some of the other points you have raised later.

    By the way, one cannot strictly draw a parallel between Chanakya and Machiavelli. In my lmited knowledge, Machiavelli’s prescriptions did not have any element of morality while Chanakya’s advice was based on justice and righteousness (“Dharma”).

  6. VoP says:

    Sanjeev’ji

    What went wrong?

    Some answers can be found in this essay..
    http://sankrant.sulekha.com/blog/post/2004/03/are-indians-corrupt.htm

  7. Dear Shantanu

    State policy should not be linked in any way with concepts of morality. The idea that Dharma (or anyone’s ideas of morality) is in some way superior to a system of the **Rule of Law** can be easily questioned. As I explain in The Discovery of Freedom (http://discovery.sabhlokcity.com/) at length, while concepts of morality can and should inform state policy (law), the policy (law) must be determined through a complex analysis that is much broader and more general than the concepts of morality as commonly propounded, most importantly that includes the principles of freedom. Plus it should be determined through democratic consent.

    I am not draw any direct parallel between Chanakya and Machiavelli but in a sense both considered human nature as a direct part of their analysis and so they can both be thought of as pre-liberals. Both advanced political science or the science of the state. Both came to very similar conclusions about the role of the king and why the king should be good – for pragmatic reasons if nothing else. But both failed to articulate the comprehensive theory of the state from today’s vantage point of knowledge.

    ==
    Dear VoP, I had a quick look at the linked article but that doesn’t seem to say anything to say about why India abandoned sceptical thinkers 2500 years ago.

    The analysis I am looking for would be primarily a historical analysis, looking at ancient scriptures and debates, and aiming to investigate why India became so badly ossified 2000 years ago with the result that its fertile and independent mind – that preceded the Greek revolution – was soon lost in feeble and meaningless parroting of what had been said or written in the past.

    I refer primarily to Charvaka and various early India schools of sceptical philosophy here, not so much to Buddhism and definitely not to Vedanta which (despite what Swami Suddhananada makes it out to be) is not a bastion of critical thinking but a belief system – although quite exceptionally rational in its refusal to accept any story of miracles, for instance.

    The article cited does not touch upon these issues.

    Regards
    Sanjeev

  8. Khandu Patel says:

    Hindu and Greek thinking was bound to have influenced each other in their ancient engagements but their distinctiveness should not be doubted either. There is no reason to think that Hindu philosophy was inferior but neither could it be said to have been superior. It is the direction that they took subsequently which was to have profound influence on the world.

    The Greek achievement was to detach philosophy from religion. That was because Plato and Aristotle in their teachings established a rational basis for thought which is impossible without detaching it from religion. This also freed it religion to provide the fertile ground on which scientific ideas was to be planted. Greece could do this because as a democracy not given to the cult of kings but paid the price for turmoil in its political system. I am afraid we had to wait until British rule to blow away the cobs of obscurantism into which Hindu society had sunk.

    Sophistry in Greece came to be realised as a clever but low form of debating which enabled manipulators to profit in their litigious legal system. The Hindu legal approach was rather static and traditional in comparison as Hindu customary practices continue to this day.

    I no not doubt the genius of Hindu thought but the reality of it is that it impacted very little on the thinking of Hindu society in the way that Western society was transformed by Greek thought. This is precisely the problem we face today in Indian society because it is the lowest form of life that is dominant.

  9. Kaffir says:

    =>
    I refer primarily to Charvaka and various early India schools of sceptical philosophy here [..]
    =>

    Heh. 😀
    Looks like all Indian atheists, “rationalists” and Randians experience a quickening of the pulse and a fluttering of the heart when they come across Charvakas. Though so little is known about them, and hardly any of their writings survive, so they seem to easily become the Rorschach on which one can project anything and everything.

  10. B Shantanu says:

    @ Sanjeev: Two quick points…

    1] I am not sure that Chanakya “failed to articulate the comprehensive theory of the state…” but I will refrain from commenting until I have read a bit more.

    2] The idea that Dharma (or anyone’s ideas of morality) is in some way superior to a system of the **Rule of Law** can be easily questioned

    Well, “Dharma” is the “Rule of Law”..I think you missed this post: Understanding “Dharma”